Ideology and Rationality in the History of the Life Sciences
Publié le 07/01/2023
Extrait du document
«
Ideology and Rationality in the History of the
Life Sciences
Extrait automatique
Georges Canguilhem
translated by Arthur Goldhammer
The MIT Press
Cambridge, Massachusetts
London, .England
--�
068182
English translation copyright© 1988 Massachusetts Institute of
Technology
Originally published under the title Ideologie et rationalite dans l'histoire
des sciences de la vie: Nouvelles etudes d'histoire et de philosophie des
sciences, copyright© 1977 Librairie Philosophique J.
Vrin, Paris,
France.
All rights reserved.
No part of this book may be reproduced in any form
or by any electronic or mechanical means, including photocopying,
recording, or information storage and retrieval, without permission in
writing from the publisher.
This book was typeset by Graphic Composition Inc.
and was printed and bound by Halliday Lithograph
in the United States of America.
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Canguilhem, Georges,
l 904-
Ideology and rationality in the history of the life sciences.
Translation of: Ideologie et rationalite clans l'histoire des sciences de
la vie.
Bibliography: p.
Includes index.
I.
Life sciences-History.
QH305.C2613
1988
ISBN 0-262-03137-X
2.
Life sciences-Philosophy.
574'.09
88-610
I.
Title.
Contents
Translator's Preface
vii
Preface
ix
Introduction: The Role of Epistemology in
Contemporary History of Science
I
l
Scientific and Medical Ideologies in the
Nineteenth Century
l
2
3
II
What Is a Scientific Ideology?
John Brown's System: An Example of Medical
Ideology
Bacteriology and the End of Nineteenth-Century
"Medical Theory"
27
41
SI
Triumphs of Biological Rationality in the
Nineteenth and Twentieth Centuries
4
The Development of the Concept of Biological
Regulation in the Eighteenth and Nineteenth
Centuries
81
Vl
5
6
On the History of the Life Sciences since Darwin
The Question of Normality in the History of
Biological Thought
Sources
Index
CONTENTS
1 47
Translator's Preface
Georges Canguilhem was born in I904.
He studied and
began to teach philosophy but while teaching decided to
work toward a medical degree.
His reasons are worth
noting:
It is not necessarily to learn more about men�al illness that
a professor of philosophy will take an interest in medicine.
Nor is it necessarily to practi�e a scientific discipline.
What
I expected from medicine was nothing other than an intro
duction to concrete human problems.
Medicine seemed to
me then, and still seems to me now, a technique or an art
at the crossroads of several sciences more than a science in
the strict sense of the word.
Two problems-that of the
relation between science and technology, and that of norms
and normality-could, I thought, be more precisely for
mulated and more fully elucidated by someone with med
ical training .
.
.
.
The present work [his I943 thesis, The
Normal and the Pathologican is therefore an effort to in
tegrate some of the methods and results of medicine into
philosophical speculation.
Canguilhem with his life's work has admirably ful
filled this statement of intention.
Along with Gaston Bach
elard he has been one of the primary influences in the
reorien�ation of French philosophy in recent years.
It was
·Bachelard who introduced.the concept of an "epistemolog
ical break," a concept whose importance and usefulness
Canguilhem has demonstrated in his own way.
But Can
guilhem's work also shows how philosophy can span the
vm
coupure, so to speak, in order to reestablish continuity at
another level.
For Canguilhem , error is the truth of the past
transcended, and he is able to show in concrete detail why
the history of science should be studied not as a steady
march toward truth but as a process of formation and re
formation of concepts and models.
His method is more
easily grasped in action than through description, and
there is perhaps no better introduction to his work than
the essay (included here) entitled "Bacteriology and the
End of Nineteenth-Century 'Medical Theory.' "
In l 95 5 Canguilhem succeeded Bachelard as director
of the Institut d'Histoire des Sciences et des Techniques, a
position that he held until his retirement a few years ago.
Perhaps the most noted of the younger philosophers influ
enced by his thought was the late Michel Foucault, who
wrote of his debt to Canguilhem's pioneering work.
Inter
ested readers may wish to consult Le Normal et le patho
logique (1966, containing the 1943 thesis and later essays
and now available in English), La Formation du concept
de re"flexe ( 1955, reissued 1977), La Connaissance de la vie
(1952, 1965), Etudes d'histoire et de philosophie des sci
ences ( 1968), and the volume from which the present
translation was made, Ideologie et rationalite dans l'his
toire des sciences de la vie (1977).
Canguilhem also pro
vided a preface to a recent edition of Claude Bernard's
Le�ons sur les phenomenes de la vie communs aux ani
maux et aux vegetaux (1966).
TRANSLATOR'S PREFACE
Preface
To err is human, to persist in error is diabolical.
It is not
up to me to decide the degree of error embodied in the
texts gathered here.
I am surely too old to make public
confession of my mistakes, to proclaim my allegiance to
newly instituted epistemological authorities at the cost of
renouncing methodological axioms that I borrowed some
forty years ago and subsequently exploited in my own way
and at my own risk, not without emendation, revision, and
reorientation.
In 1967-68, under the influence of work of Michel
Fouc�ult and Louis Althusser, I introduced the concept of
scientific ideology into my lectures.
This was not simply a
mark of my interest in and acceptance of the original con
tributions of those two thinkers to the canons of scientific
history.
It was also a way of refurbishing without rejecting
the lessons of a teacher whose books I read but whose lec
tures I was never able to attend.
For whatever liberties my
young colleagues may have taken with the teachings of
Gaston Bachelard, their work was inspired by and built
on his.
l do not believe, therefore, that the reader of my first
Etudes ·d'histoire et de philosophie des sciences (Studies in
the History and Philosophy of the Sciences) will fin.cl in
x
these essays signs of change or evolution in my thinking.':
As for the question whether my indifference to the devel
opment of a history that would substitute for the distinc
tion between science and philosophy (or, in other words,
between science and literature) a notion of their mutual
interpenetration should or should not earn me the distinc
tion of being a "conceptualist fossil," I must admit I do not
much care.
When one's own insignificant research has led
one to recognize the existence of discontinuity in history, it
would be inappropriate to refuse to recognize discontinui
ties in the history of history.
To each his own discontinuity,
his own revolutions in the world of scholarship.
On the other hand I should like very much to answer
a question that has been raised by no one but myself.
.Ihe_
author of The Archaeology of Knowledge, whose analysis
of scientific ideology I have found quite useful, has aistin
guished several "thresholds of transformation" in the his
tory of knowledge: a threshold of positivity, a threshold
of epistemologization, a threshold of scientificity, and a
threshold of formalization.1 In my published work I am
not sure that I have distinguished as carefully as Michel
Foucault might wish among the various thresholds crossed
by the disciplines I have studied.
It seems to me in any case
that, the claims of certain geneticists notwithstanding,
none of those disciplines has yet crossed the threshold of
formalization.2 Un�ike Foucault, however, I do not believe
that experimental medicine as practiced by Claude Bernard
and microbiology as practiced by Louis Pasteur were
equally inadequate in their contribution to making a sci
ence of clinical medicine.
I readily admit that I failed to
pay adequate attention to the question of thresholds of
*[Etudes d'histoire et de philosophie des sciences was p�blished
by Librairie Vrin in 1968.
The French edition of the present work
bears the subtitle Nouvelles etudes d'histoire et de philosophie
des sciences.-Trans.]
PREFACE
x1
transformation.
But nineteenth-century medicine and bi
ology lend themselves less readily than, say, nineteenth
century chemistry to dissection of the conditions that made
"progress" possible.
One can still argue, I think, that Ber
nard's physiological medicine exhibits a case in which "ep
istemologization," at the hands of a Bernard himself in love
with philosophizing, raced far in "advance" even of posi
tive empirical results.
By contrast, Pasteur, a chemist rather
than a physician, was primarily interested in making a pos
itive contribution to research and not unduly concerned
with developing a consistent epistemology.
3
It may be, finally, that my analyses are not sufficiently
subtle or rigorous.
I leave it to the reader to decide whether
this is a question of discretion, sloth, or incapacity.
Notes
l
See Michel Foucault, L'Archeologie du savoir, pp.
243-247.
2
Cf.
J.
H.
Woodger, Axiomatic Method in Biology (Cambridge:
1937), and "Formalization in Biology," Logique et analyse, new
series, l (August 1 9 5 8 ) ."
3
Cf.
F.
Dagognet, Methodes et doctrine dans /'oeuvre de Pasteur
(Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1967), conclusion.
G.C.
June 1977
PREFACE
Ideology and Rationality in the History of the
Life Sciences
Introduction: The Role of Epistemology in
Contemporary History of Science
To anyone who would examine the relations between epis
temology and the history of science, one fact stands out
above all others: namely, that we possess at present more
manifestoes and programs of research than we do hard
facts.
Statements of intention are numerous, concrete re
sults meager.
Compared with the history of science, a discipline
with a history of its own, epistemology at first sight seems
to find itself in a false position.
Chronologically, the history
of science owes nothing to the philosophical discipline that
appears to have acquired the name epistemology in 1854.1
Montucla's Histoire des mathematiques ( 175S), Bailly's
Histoire de l'astronomie (1775- 178 2), and Kurt Sprengel's
Versuch einer pragmatischen .Geschichte der Arzneikunde
( 1792- 1803) were all written without reference to any sys
tem of critical or normative concepts.
No doubt all these
works were informed, whether their authors were aware
of it or not, by a period consciousness, impersonally for
mulated in the doctrine of infinite perfectibility of the hu
man spirit and based on an almost unbroken series of
revolutions in cosmology, mathematics, and physiology- ·
.
revolutions associated with the names Copernicus, Galileo,
Descartes, Harvey, Newton, Leibniz, and Lavoisier.
On
2
grounds of continuity it was therefore legitimate to believe
in further scientific progress to come: Although Spr'engel
(the date being 1792) explicitly alludes to critical philoso
phy in the introduction to his history of medicine, he men
tions it simply as a doctrine in which certain physicians
happen to be well versed, just as certain of their predeces
sors were well versed in dogmatic, empirical, or skeptical
philosophy, rather than as a new and effective instrument
for judging the validity of scientific methods.
ence there
is no point in reproaching eighteenth- and ·nineteenth
century historians of science for not having employed any
of the epistemological concepts that today's philosophers
are attempting to enforce as rules ·for writing scientific
history.
Among historians of science, those who dislike _the
scrutiny of their discipline by epistemologists have not
been remiss in pointing out that epistemology, itself....
»
↓↓↓ APERÇU DU DOCUMENT ↓↓↓
Liens utiles
- VIE ET L’œUVRE DE SIGMUND FREUD (La) [The Life and Work of Sigmund Freud]. (résumé)
- the origins and the history of the european union
- Robinson Crusoe (extrait) Daniel Defoe (...) In a little time I began to speak to him, and teach him to speak to me; and, first, I made him know his name should be Friday, which was the day I saved his life.
- erbs Greek The mythic power of herbs to transform people and to restore life to the dead features prominently in several Greek myths.
- Earth Mother A symbol in many ancient myth systems of the Earth, the source of all life and the power to create life.