Devoir de Philosophie

Axiom of choice

Publié le 25/01/2010

Extrait du document

The axiom of choice is a mathematical postulate about sets: for each family of non-empty sets, there exists a function selecting one member from each set in the family. If those sets have no member in common, it postulates that there is a set having exactly one element in common with each set in the family. First formulated in 1904, the axiom of choice was highly controversial among mathematicians and philosophers, because it epitomized 'non-constructive' mathematics. Nevertheless, as time passed, it had an increasingly broad range of consequences in many branches of mathematics.

  • Axiome : principe dont on pose la vérité au départ d'une démons-tration chargée d'établir la vérité de ses conséquences logiques.

« choice is consistent with the usual axioms of set theory, but also independent from them. 2 Philosophical questions surrounding the axiom Today almost all mathematicians accept the axiom of choice, although many still remark when they use it.

Earlier, Zermelo defended the axiom against its critics on two grounds: its usefulness and its self-evidence.

He remarked that it had already been widely used, without being formulated explicitly.

Such widespread use, he argued, could only be explained by the axiom's self-evidence. Opponents of the axiom had various views.

Some, such as Emile Borel, accepted the axiom when applied to a denumerable family of sets, but rejected it when applied to a family of larger cardinality, such as the set of all real numbers.

Others, including René Baire, tentatively accepted the real numbers but argued against the existence of the set of all subsets of the real numbers, from which subsets Zermelo's choices were made.

Many opponents rejected the axiom because it provided no rule for making the choices.

Apparently thinking of axioms in the traditional way as self-evident truths, they often failed to understand that the axiom is needed precisely when no rule is available. Opponents were encouraged by the axiom's counter-intuitive consequences.

The most vivid of these was the Banach-Tarski paradox, whereby a sphere S can be decomposed into a finite number of pieces and reassembled into two spheres each of the same size as S.

The three-dimensionality is important here, since such a decomposition cannot be done with a two-dimensional figure such as a circle.

Euclidean geometry also plays a role, since hyperbolic geometry (in which the parallel postulate is false) allows the various counter-intuitive decompositions without using the axiom. The irony for the axiom's opponents was that if set theory is understood in a sufficiently constructivist way, then the axiom is true.

In the extreme case, when all sets are finite, the axiom is true but trivial.

If set theory is restricted to Gödel's constructible sets, then again the axiom is true but now distinctly non-trivial.

It is only when set theory is taken in a non-constructive way that the axiom might be false.

Even in intuitionism, various restricted forms of the axiom are true, but their meaning is changed since the underlying logic is not first-order logic (see Intuitionism ). 3 Mathematical theorems that need the axiom Zermelo introduced the axiom of choice to prove the well-ordering theorem: every set can be well-ordered (see Set theory ).

Previously Georg Cantor had assumed this well-ordering theorem as a 'law of thought' , but mathematicians had been sceptical.

Zermelo showed that the well-ordering theorem follows from an axiom that is conceptually much simpler: the axiom of choice. The axiom of choice is vital to the arithmetic of infinite cardinal numbers.

In particular, it is equivalent to the proposition that if two cardinals are unequal, then one is greater than the other.

It is needed in order to define the. »

↓↓↓ APERÇU DU DOCUMENT ↓↓↓

Liens utiles