Chinese Confucian philosophy is primarily a set of ethical ideas oriented toward practice. Characteristically, it
stresses the traditional boundaries of ethical responsibility and dao, or the ideal of the good human life as a
whole. It may be characterized as an ethics of virtue in the light of its conception of dao and de (virtue).
Comprising the conceptial framework of Confucian ethics are notions of basic virtues such as ren (benevolence),
yi (rightness, righteousness), and li (rites, propriety). There are also notions of dependent virtues such as filiality,
loyalty, respectfulness and integrity. Basic virtues are considered fundamental, leading or action-guiding, cardinal
and the most comprehensive. In the classic Confucian sense, ren pertains to affectionate concern for the well-being
of fellows in one's community. Notably, ren is often used in an extended sense by major Song and Ming Confucians
as interchangeable with dao for the ideal of the universe as a moral community. Yi pertains to the sense of
rightness, especially exercised in coping with changing circumstances of human life, those situations that fall
outside the scope of li. Li focuses on rules of proper conduct, which have three functions: delimiting, supportive
and ennobling. That is, the li define the boundaries of proper behaviour, provide opportunities for satisfying
desires of moral agents within these boundaries, and encourage the development of noble characters which
markedly embody cultural refinement and communal concerns. The li are the depository of insights of the
Confucian tradition as a living ethical tradition. This tradition is subject to changing interpretation governed by
the exercise of quan or the weighing of circumstances informed by the sense of rightness (yi).
However, the common Confucian appeal to historical events and paradigmatic individuals is criticized because of
lack of understanding of the ethical uses of such a historical appeal. The pedagogical use stresses the study of the
classics in terms of the standards of ren, yi and li. Learning, however, is not a mere acquisition of knowledge, but
requires understanding and insight. Also, the companion study of paradigmatic individuals is important, not only
because they point to models of emulation but also because they are, so to speak, exemplary personifications of the
spirits of ren, yi and li. Moreover, they also function as reminders of moral learning and conduct that appeal
especially to what is deemed in the real interest of the learner. The rhetorical use of the historical appeal is
basically an appeal to plausible presumptions, or shared beliefs and trustworthiness. These presumptions are
subject to further challenge, but they can be accepted as starting points in discourse. The elucidative use of
historical appeal purports to clarify the relevance of the past for the present. Perhaps most important for
argumentative discourse is the evaluative function of historical appeal. It focuses our knowledge and
understanding of our present problematic situations as a basis for exerting the unexamined claims based on the
past as a guidance for the present. Thus, both the elucidative and evaluative uses of historical appeal are critical
and attentive to evidential grounding of ethical claims.
Because of its primary ethical orientation and its influence on traditional Chinese life and thought, Confucianism
occupies a pre-eminent place in the history of Chinese philosophy. The core of Confucian thought lies in the
teachings of Confucius (551-479 BC) contained in the Analects (Lunyu), along with the brilliant and divergent
contributions of Mencius (372?-289 BC) and Xunzi (fl. 298-238 BC), as well as the Daxue (Great Learning) and the
Zhongyong (Doctrine of the Mean), originally chapters in the Liji (Book of Rites). Significant and original
developments, particularly along a quasi-metaphysical route, are to be found in the works of Zhou Dunyi
(1017-73), Zhang Zai (1020-77), Cheng Hao (1032-85), Cheng Yi (1033-1107), Zhu Xi (1130-1200), Lu
Xiangshan (1139-93), and Wang Yangming (1472-1529). Li Gou (1009-59), Wang Fuzhi (1619-92), and Dai Zhen
(1723-77) have also made noteworthy contributions to the critical development of Confucian philosophy. In the
twentieth century, the revitalization and transformation of Confucian philosophy has taken a new turn in response
to Western philosophical traditions. Important advances have been made by Feng Youlan, Tang Junyi, Thomé H.
Fang, and Mou Zongsan. Most of the recent works in critical reconstruction are marked by a self-conscious
concern with analytic methodology and the relevance of existentialism, phenomenology, and hermeneutics. Still
lacking is a comprehensive and systematic Confucian theory informed by both the history and the problems of
Western philosophy.
1 The conceptual framework
A student or scholar of moral philosophy, approaching the classical core of Confucian ethics for the first time, is
likely to be faced with a major difficulty in the lack of systematic exposition of basic Confucian notions such as
ren (benevolence), li (rites), and yi (rightness), and their interconnection. Unlike major Western philosophers,
Confucian thinkers are not concerned with definitions. As William Theodore de Bary (1970: v) has pointed out,
most Chinese thinkers are not interested in the definition and analysis of concepts: ‘generally, the more crucial or
central the idea, the greater the ambiguity'. Instead, they are concerned with the expansive uses of ideas that
suggest the widest possible range of meaning.
From the point of view of contemporary moral philosophy, this pervasive feature of Confucian discourses may
appear to be an anomaly, given the classical emphasis on the right use of terms (zhengming). A serious student of
the works of Xunzi, the one classical Confucian generally considered to be the most rationalistic and systematic
philosopher, will be frustrated in the attempt to find definitions, in the sense of necessary and sufficient conditions,
for the application of basic Confucian terms. This fact is all the more surprising in view of Xunzi's recurrent
employment of certain definitional locutions or quasi-definitional formulas for explaining his theses on human
nature and the mind. Like most major Confucians, Xunzi has a pragmatic attitude toward the use of language, that
is, the uses of terms that require explanation are those that are liable to misunderstanding in the context of
particular discourse. The Confucian explanations of the use of ethical terms are context-dependent and are
addressed to a particular rather than universal audience.
Two different assumptions underlying this attitude toward language may account for the absence of Chinese
interest in context-independent explanation of the use of ethical terms. First, there is an assumption of the primacy
of practice implicit in the Confucian doctrine of the unity of knowledge and action (zhixing heyi). Definition, in the
sense of meaning explanation, is a matter of practical rather than theoretical necessity. This assumption does not
depreciate the importance of theoretical inquiry, but rather focuses on its relevance to the requirements of practice,
particularly those that promote unity and harmony among people in the community. Such requirements vary in
time and place. A viable ethical theory is thus subject to pragmatic assessment in the light of changing
circumstances. In general, ethical requirements cannot be stated in terms of absolute or fixed principles or rules. It
is this assumption of the primacy of practice that renders plausible Donald Munro's claim that the consideration
important to the Chinese is the behavioural implications of the belief or proposition in question (Munro 1969).
What effect does adherence to the belief have on people? What implications for social action can be drawn from
the statement? In Confucianism, there was no thought of ‘knowing' that did not entail some consequence for
action.
Related to the primacy of practice is the assumption that reasoned discourse may legitimately appeal to what
Nicholas Rescher calls ‘plausible presumptions,' that is, an appeal to shared knowledge, belief or experience, as
well as to established or operative standards of discourse (Rescher 1977: 38). For Confucian thinkers, most of
these presumptions, at least among the well-educated, represent the shared understanding of a common tradition
and a living cultural heritage. These presumptions are often suppressed and mainly form the background of
discourse. Thus Confucian reasoning and argumentation appears to be highly vague and inexplicit. From the
Aristotelian point of view, Confucian reasoning is ‘rhetorical', as it frequently involves enthymemes and
arguments from examples.
Given the assumptions of the primacy of practice and appeal to plausible presumptions, any attempt at introducing
Confucian ethics to students of Western philosophy involves a basic task in philosophical reconstruction. This is a
task in constructive interpretation, not only in providing a general characterization but also in reshaping the basic
notions and concerns of Confucian ethics in response to some problems of moral philosophy. Such an exploration
serves two important and connected aims: first, a plausible explication of the Confucian outlook in philosophically
relevant idioms, and second, a critical development of Confucian ethical thought.
2 An ethics of virtue: dao and de
While major Confucianists (for example, Mencius and Xunzi) differ in their conceptions of human nature in
relation to conduct, most of them accept Confucius' ideal of a well-ordered society based on good government (
Xing; Mencius; Xunzi). Good government is responsive to the basic needs of the people, to issues of wise
management of natural resources and to just distribution of burdens and benefits. In this vision of socio-political
order, special emphasis is put on harmonious human relationships (lun) in accord with de, virtues or standards of
excellence. This vision is often called dao, a term that has been appropriated by different classical schools of
Chinese thought, including Daoism and Legalism ( Legalist philosophy, Chinese; Daoist Philosophy). In the
Analects, dao is sometimes used as a verb, meaning ‘to guide'; sometimes it is used as a concrete noun, meaning
literally ‘road'. In the latter sense, it can be rendered as ‘way'. But in distinct Confucian ethical usage, as
commonly acknowledged by commentators, it is dao as an abstract noun that is meant, and more especially in the
evaluative rather than descriptive sense, that is, as referring to the ethical ideal of a good human life as a whole
( Dao).
Throughout its long history, Confucianism has stressed character formation or personal cultivation of virtues (de)
( De). Thus it seems appropriate to characterize Confucian ethics as an ethics of virtue, not an ethics of rules or
principles. To avoid misunderstanding, two explanations are in order. In the first place, the Confucian focus on the
centrality of virtues assumes that the notion of de can be rendered as ‘virtue'. In the second place, this focus does
not depreciate the importance of rule-governed conduct ( Moral development).
Sinologists differ in their interpretation of the Confucian use of de. Some insist that de should be construed as
‘power', ‘force' or ‘potency', and in Confucian usage it should be qualified as moral in contrast to physical force.
Others argue for ‘virtue' in the distinctively ethical sense, as pertaining to the excellence of a character trait or
disposition. Interestingly, these two construals of de are not incompatible in the light of some English uses of
‘virtue' ( Virtue ethics). In Webster's Third New International Dictionary, for example, the sixth definition of
‘virtue' is: ‘an active quality or power whether of physical or of moral nature; the capacity or power adequate to
the production of a given effect', and the fifth definition is: ‘a characteristic, quality, or trait known or felt to be
excellent'. The Oxford English Dictionary likewise offers as definitions ‘a good quality' and ‘efficacy; inherent
power'. Both these senses of ‘virtue' are found in the classical Chinese uses of de.
There is, of course, the value-neutral sense of de that leaves open the question whether personal traits or qualities
merit ethical approval, and this question is reflected in the distinction, still current in Modern Chinese, between
meide and ede. The former pertains to ‘beautiful' or ‘commendable' de, and the latter to its contrary. Meide are
those traits that are acquired through personal cultivation. The Encyclopedia Dictionary of the Chinese Language
offers the following two entries for de in the ethical sense, one suggested by an interpretation of its homophone,
meaning ‘to get' or ‘to obtain', found in the Liji (Book of Rites): ‘that which is obtained in the heart-and-mind as a
result of personal cultivation', and ‘the nature that is formed after successful personal cultivation'. Both these
definitions involve meide, commendable, acquired qualities or traits of character, much in the sense of David
Hume's ‘personal merits' ( Hume, D.) Ede, on the other hand, are personal demerits or ‘detestable' qualities of
character.
Also important is the sense of de as power or force, in view of the Confucian notion of junzi (ethically superior or
paradigmatic individuals). By virtue of ethical achievement, a junzi possesses the power of attraction or influence
indicative of effective agency ( Moral agents). As Confucius remarks, the junzi, equipped with the virtues (de),
never stands alone: ‘He is bound to have neighbours.' ‘The virtue (de) of the gentleman (junzi) is like the wind;
the virtue (de) of the small man is like grass. Let the wind blow over the grass and it is sure to bend' (Analects
12.19, in Lau 1979: 115-16). In sum, the Confucian notion of de can be properly construed as ethical virtues that
possess a dual aspect: an achieved condition of a person through self-cultivation of commendable character traits
in accordance with the ideal dao, and a condition that is deemed to have the peculiar potency or power of efficacy
in influencing the course of human life. The difficult problem is to present the Confucian dao and de as an ethics
of virtue with a coherent conceptual scheme.
3 Basic notions and the problem of conceptual unity
The Analects, a composite work, is commonly considered the main and most reliable source of Confucius'
teachings ( Confucius). It bequeaths to the Chinese tradition a large and complex ethical vocabulary, which
contains a significant number of virtue (de) terms with implicit reference to the Confucian ideal of dao. Terms
such as ren (benevolence), yi (rightness) and li (rites) seem to occupy a central position both in the Analects and
throughout the history of Confucian discourse. Until recent times, however, few philosophical scholars of
Confucianism attended to the problem of conceptual explication and the unity of these basic notions, that is, their
presumed interconnection or interdependence in the light of dao as an ideal, unifying perspective. While most
Confucian terms for particular virtues can be rendered into English without the need of elaborate explanation - for
example, xiao (filiality), yong (courage), wei (dignity), zhong (fidelity), ci (kindness), jing (respectfulness) - the
apparently basic notions (ren, li and yi) are not amenable to the simple expedience of translation and thus pose a
problem for conceptual analysis and interpretation. Moreover, existing translations of these terms ineluctably
embody the writer's interpretation, a sort of implicit commentary, representing the writer's prior understanding of
the translated texts.
Similarly, an explication of basic Confucian notions involves philosophical commentary, a familiar feature in the
development of the history of Chinese thought. However, attempts at explication have been beset by a formidable
difficulty, especially in defining the basic concepts of the Confucian framework. The pioneering study of the
conceptual aspect of Confucian ethics is Chen Daqi's Kongzi xueshuo (Teachings of Confucius) (Chen 1976).
Chen reminds us that prior to interpreting the ideas of Confucius, it is essential to inquire into the conceptual status
of some recurrent terms in the text. For determining the centrality or basic status of notions or concepts, Chen
proposes four criteria, according to which basic concepts are (1) fundamental, (2) leading or guiding, (3) the most
important (cardinal) or (4) the most comprehensive.
Fundamental concepts suggest the distinction between basic and derivative concepts. However, it is more
plausible and accords better with Chen's discussion to construe his distinction as one between basic and dependent
concepts. Given our characterization of Confucian ethics as an ethics of virtues, this is a conceptual distinction
between basic and dependent virtues. A concept may depend on another for its ethical significance without being a
logical derivation. For instance, one cannot derive the concept of love from ren, yet its ethical significance
depends on its connection with ren. This is perhaps the principal ground for Zhu Xi's famous contention that ren
cannot be equated with love, for it is the rationale of love (ai zhi li) ( Zhu Xi).
Leading or guiding concepts recall the purport of ethical terms as guides for action, informing the Confucian agent
that the enduring significance of ethical endeavours lies in the pursuit of dao or the ideal of the good human life as
a whole. Cardinal concepts and comprehensive concepts are the chief mark of basic ethical concepts.
Comprehensive concepts also raise an issue in Confucian scholarship. Perhaps the issue can be settled if
comprehensiveness is ascribed to dao or ren in the broad sense as signifying the holistic, ideal unifying perspective
of Confucian discourse. Again, consider Zhu Xi's thesis that ren (in the broad sense) embraces the four: ren (in the
narrow sense), yi (rightness), li (rites) and zhi (wisdom). In terms of an ethics of virtue, the fundamental distinction
is the distinction between cardinal and dependent virtues. Accordingly, Chen proposes that in addition to dao and
de, the Confucian scheme consists of ren, li and yi as the basic, cardinal concepts. This thesis is well-supported by
the recurrence of such concepts and their fundamental importance throughout the history of Confucianism.
4 The ethical framework of Confucianism
The foregoing pertains to the question of identifying basic, cardinal concepts as contrasted with dependent
concepts. A more formidable problem remains as to how these basic concepts are related to one another. The
following discussion presents a sketch of a philosophical reconstruction, which is essentially a conceptual
experiment. The sketch offers a general characterization of Confucian ethics as a form of virtue ethics, and
provides a sample of how such basic notions as li and yi can be shaped in response to questions deemed important
for the development of a Confucian moral philosophy.
The Confucian ethical framework comprises the five basic concepts: dao, de, ren, yi and li. The best initial
approach is to regard these, with a minimum of interpretation, as ‘focal notions', that is, terms that function like
focal lenses for conveying distinct though not unrelated centres of ethical concern. As generic terms, focal notions
are amenable to specification in particular contexts, thus acquiring specific or narrower senses. This distinction is
an adaptation of Xunzi's distinction between generic terms (gongming) and specific terms (bieming). However, a
term used as a specific term in one context may in another context be used as a generic term subject to further
specification. In other words, the use of a term in either the generic or specific sense is entirely relative to the
speaker's purpose on a particular occasion, rather than to any theory concerning the intrinsic characters of terms or
the essential attributes of things.
As noted earlier, dao is an evaluative term. Its focal point of interest lies in the Confucian vision of the good
human life as a whole or the ideal of human excellence. Commonly rendered as ‘the way', dao is functionally
equivalent to the ideal ‘way of life'. Unlike other basic terms, dao is most distinctive as an abstract, formal term in
the highest generic sense, that is, subject to general specification by way of such virtue (de) words as ren, li and yi.
As de is an individual achievement through personal cultivation, when a person succeeds in realizing dao, they
have attained such basic de as ren, li and yi. The specification of de, apart from ren, li and yi, can take a variety of
forms or dependent virtues such as filiality, respectfulness or trustworthiness. In this sense, de is an abstract noun
like dao, but it depends on dao for its distinctive character. De is thus functionally equivalent to ethical virtue.
Thus, the opening remark of the Daxue (Great Learning) points out that the way of great learning or adult, ethical
education lies in the clear exemplification of the virtues (ming mingde) ( Daxue; Moral education; Moral
development). With its emphasis on dao and de, Confucian ethics is properly characterized as an ethics of virtue,
but more informatively as an ethics of ren, li and yi, relative to their concrete specification or particularization by
terms of dependent virtues (for example, filiality, respectfulness, integrity). As generic, focal terms, ren, li and yi
are specific terms relative to dao as a generic term. Differently put, implicit in Chen's account is a distinction
between basic, interdependent virtues (ren, li and yi) and dependent virtues (filiality, respectfulness and so on)
(Chen 1976). As indicated earlier, the latter are dependent in the sense that their ethical import depends on direct
or indirect reference to one or more of the basic, interdependent virtues of ren, li and yi ( Virtue ethics).
5 Ren
While ren, commonly translated as ‘benevolence', has a long history of conceptual evolution and interpretation, as
a focal notion it centres its ethical interest on love and care for one's fellows, that is, an affectionate concern for
the well-being of others - the one persistent idea in the Confucian tradition. For this reason, English translators
often render ren as ‘benevolence', suggestive of the use of ‘benevolence' in Francis Hutcheson and David Hume.
Perhaps a more literal translation of ren, however, is ‘human-heartedness' or ‘humanity', since ren is basically an
idea of love or concern for the well-being of human community, a specification of the concrete significance of the
Confucian dao ( Community and communitarianism §1). This core meaning of ren as fellow-feeling is found in
the Analects; it is reported that Confucius once said to his disciple Zengzi, ‘My dao has one thread that runs
through it.' Zengzi construed this dao to consist of zhong and shu, an interpretation widely acknowledged as a
method for pursuing ren (Analects 4.15, in Lau 1979: 74) While the relation betweenzhong and shu has divergent
interpretations, zhong may be rendered as ‘doing one's best', and shu as ‘consideration' (of other people's feelings
and desires). In this light, Confucian ethics displays a concern for both self-regarding and other-regarding virtues.
However, the acquisition of these virtues presupposes a locus in which these particular, dependent virtues are
exercised. Thus among the dependent virtues, filiality, brotherhood or sisterhood are primary, for the family is the
natural home and the foundation for the extension of ren-affection. Thus friendship is viewed as a fundamental
human relationship along with those of husband-wife and parent-child. In Song and Ming Confucianism (for
example, in Cheng Hao and Wang Yangming), dao is sometimes used interchangeably with ren. In this manner,
ren attained the status of a supreme, all-embracing ethical ideal of the well-being of every existent thing, human or
non-human, animate or inanimate. Confucius' vision of a well-ordered human society is transformed into the
vision of the universe as a moral community. In this conception, anything that is an actual or potential object of
human attention is considered an object of human concern. Exploitation of human and natural resources must be
subject to evaluation in terms of dao as an all embracing ethical ideal of existence. This ideal of dao makes no
specific demands on ordinary humans. For the most part, conflict of values is left to individual determination,
though the welfare of the parents is always the first consideration. Thus, the concrete significance of dao is open to
the exercise of yi, the agent's sense of rightness.
6 Yi and li
The exercise of yi, usually rendered as righteousness or rightness, depends on ethical education based on daotong
or the tradition of the community of interpretation; that is, the reasoned interpretation of the educated members of
the community informed by sensus communis, a sense of common interest, a regard for dao as the ideal unifying
perspective. Disagreement or dispute on the pragmatic import of dao is expected, as members of the community of
interpretation have their own conceptions of human excellence (shan) and possibilities of fulfilment. The ethical
solution of conflict of interpretation lies in transforming the disagreement into agreement in the light of sensus
communis, not in a solution defined by agonistic debate which presumes that there are impartial judges who can
render their corporate decision in terms of majority vote. Unlike contemporary democratic polity, the majority rule
cannot be reasonably accepted as a standard for setting ethical disagreement. The ethical tradition provides the
background and guidelines to ethical conduct. Normative ethical theories have value because they provide
different ways of assessing the significance of tradition. Like the basic concepts of Confucian ethics, they are focal
notions for important centres of ethical concern, for example, duty and interest (private or public), or in recent
terminology, agent-relative and agent-neutral reasons for action ( Moral agents).
The notion of li focuses on the ritual code ( Law and ritual in Chinese philosophy). For this reason, it is
commonly rendered as ‘rites', ‘ritual', ‘propriety', or ‘ceremonials'. The ritual code is essentially a set of rules of
proper conduct pertaining to the manner or style of performance. As yi is incompatible with exclusive regard for
personal gain, the li set forth the rules of ethical responsibility. For Confucius and his followers, the li represent an
enlightened tradition. As D.C. Lau has put it:
The rites (li) were a body of rules governing action in every aspect of life and they were the repository of past
insights into morality. It is, therefore, important that one should, unless there are strong reasons to the contrary,
observe them. Though there is no guarantee that observance of the rites necessarily leads, in every case, to
behaviour that is right, the chances are it will, in fact, do so.
(Lau 1979: 20)
Yet, the ethical significance of li is determined by the presence of the spirit of ren. As Confucius once said, ‘If a
man has no ren, what has he to do with li?' (Analects 3.3, in Lau 1979: 67). Since the ritual code represents a
customary practice, the early Confucians, particularly Xunzi and the writers of some chapters in the Liji, were
concerned with providing a reasoned justification for compliance with li or traditional rules of proper conduct. As
Arthur Waley aptly remarks: ‘it was with the relation of ritual [li] as a whole to morality and not with the details
of etiquette and precedence that the early Confucianists were chiefly concerned' (Waley 1938: 67) The same
concern with reasoned justification is evident in Song and Ming Confucianists (for example, Zhu Xi and Wang
Yangming) who maintain that the significance of li (ritual) lies in its rationale (li zhi li).
The ethical significance of yi, in part, is an attempt to provide a rationale for the acceptance of li. Yi focuses
principally on what is right or fitting. The equation of yi with its homophone meaning ‘appropriateness' is explicit
in the Zhongyong, 20 ( Zhongyong), and is generally accepted by Confucianists (for example, Xunzi, Li Gou
and Zhu Xi). However, what is right or fitting depends on reasoned judgement. As Xunzi observes: ‘The person
concerned with yi follows reason' (Xunzi XV, in Li 1979: 328) Thus, yi may be construed as reasoned judgement
concerning the right thing to do in particular exigencies. Li Gou, a Song Confucian, justly reminds his readers that
yi is ‘decisive judgement' that is appropriate to the situation at hand.
In light of the foregoing, the interdependence of basic notions may be stated as follows. Given dao as the ideal of
the good human life as a whole, ren, li and yi, the basic Confucian virtues (de), are constitutive rather than mere
instrumental means to its actualization. In other words, the actualization of dao requires the co-satisfaction of the
standards expressed in ren, li and yi. Since these focal notions pertain to different foci of ethical interest, we may
also say that the actualization of dao requires a coordination of three equally important centres of ethical interest
and endeavour. The connection between these foci is one of interdependence rather than subordination. Thus in the
ideal case, ren, li and yi are mutually supportive and adherent to the same ideal of dao. When dao is in fact
realized, ren, li and yi would be deemed constituents of this condition of achievement. When, on the other hand,
one attends to the prospect of dao-realization, ren, li and yi would be regarded as complementary foci and means
to dao as an end. In sum, ren, li and yi are complementary foci of human interest.
7 The scope and functions of li
Because of its distinctive character and role in Confucian ethics and its pervasive influence in traditional China
and contemporary critique, the notion of li requires special attention ( Law and ritual in Chinese philosophy).
Implicit in the notion of li is an idea of rule-governed conduct. In the Liji (Book of Rites), the subject matter ranges
from ritual rules (or formal prescriptions) concerning mourning, sacrifices, marriage and communal festivities to
the more ordinary occasions relating to conduct towards ruler, superior, parent, elder, teacher and guest. Because
of its emphasis on the form or manner of behaviour, li is often translated as ‘religious rites', ‘ceremony',
‘deportment', ‘decorum', ‘propriety', ‘formality', ‘politeness', ‘courtesy', ‘etiquette', ‘good form' or ‘good
behaviour'. These renderings are misleading without understanding the different functions of li. At the outset, it is
important to note that for Confucians the li are an embodiment of a living cultural tradition; that is, they are subject
to modification in response to changing circumstances of society. Thus some writers of the Liji point out that the li
are the prescriptions of reason, and that any ritual rule that is deemed right and reasonable (yi) can be considered a
part of li. On one plausible interpretation, the traditional ritual code represents no more than a codification of
ethical experiences based on the concern with ren and yi. In this light, the li are in principle subject to revision or
replacement. In the spirit of Zhu Xi, we may say that a Confucian must reject ritual rules that are burdensome and
superfluous and accept those that are practicable and essential to the maintenance of a harmonious social order.
However, any reasoned attempt to revise or replace li presupposes an understanding of their functions. It is this
understanding that distinguishes the Confucian scholar from a pedant, who may have a mastery of rules without
understanding their underlying rationales. For elucidation, we rely mainly on a reconstruction of Xunzi's view,
since we find in some of his essays the most articulate concern for and defence of li as an embodiment of a living,
cultural tradition ( Xunzi).
With regard to any system of rules governing human conduct, one can always raise questions concerning its
purpose. In Confucian ethics, the li, as a set of formal prescriptions for proper behaviour, have a threefold
function: delimiting, supportive and ennobling. The delimiting function is primary, in that the li are fundamentally
directed to the prevention of human conflict. They comprise a set of constraints that delineate the boundaries of
pursuit of individual needs, desires and interests. The li purport to set forth rules of proceeding in an orderly
fashion, ultimately to promote the unity and harmony of human association in a state ruled by a sage king imbued
with the spirit of ren and yi. This orderliness consists of social distinctions or divisions in various kinds of human
relationships (lun), namely, the distinctions between ruler and minister, father and son, the eminent and the
humble, the elder and the younger, the rich and the poor, and the important and unimportant members of society.
In abstraction from the connection with ren and yi, the delimiting function of li may be compared to that of
negative moral rules or criminal laws. Like rules against killing, stealing or lying, the li impose constraints on
conduct. They create paths of obstruction, thus blocking certain moves of agents in the pursuit of their desires or
interests. The li, in effect, stipulate the conditions of eligibility or permissibility of actions. They do not prejudge
the substantive character or value of individual pursuit. They provide information on the limiting conditions of
action, but no positive guidance as to how one's desires may be properly satisfied. Put differently, the li tell agents
what goals not to pursue, but they do not tell them how to go about pursuing goals within the prescribed limits of
action.
Apart from the delimiting function, the li have also a supportive function; that is, they provide conditions or
opportunities for satisfaction of desires within the prescribed limits of action. Instead of suppressing desires, the li
provide acceptable channels or outlets for their fulfilment. In an important sense, the supportive function of li
acknowledges the integrity of our natural desires. So long as they are satisfied within the bounds of propriety, we
accept them for what they are whether reasonable or unreasonable, wise or foolish, good or bad. The main
supportive function of li is the redirection of the course of individual self-seeking activities, not the suppression of
motivating desires. Just as the delimiting function of li may be compared with that of criminal law, their supportive
function may be compared with that of procedural law, which contains rules that enable us to carry out our wishes
and desires (for example, the law of wills and contracts). The li, like these procedural rules, aid the realization of
desires without pronouncing value judgments.
The focus on the ennobling function of li is a distinctive feature of Confucian ethics and traditional Chinese culture
( Self-cultivation, Chinese theories of). The keynote of the ennobling function is ‘cultural refinement', the
education and nourishment (yang) of emotions or their transformation in accord with the spirit of ren and yi. The
characteristic concern with the form of proper behaviour is still present. However, the form stressed is not just a
matter of fitting into an established social structure or set of distinctions, nor is it a matter of methodical procedure
that facilitates the satisfaction of the agent's desires and wishes; rather, it involves the elegant form (wen) for the
expression of ethical character. In other words, the ennobling function of li is directed primarily to the
development of commendable or beautiful virtues (meide). The ‘beauty' (mei) of the expression of an ethical
character lies in the balance between emotions and form. What is deemed admirable in the virtuous conduct of an
ethically superior person (junzi) is the harmonious fusion of elegant form and feelings. In the ideal case, a
li-performance may be said to have an aesthetic dimension. In two different and related ways, a li-performance
may be said to be an object of delight. In the first place, the elegant form is something that delights our senses. It
can be contemplated with delight quite apart from the expressed emotional quality. In the second place, when we
attend to the emotion or emotional quality expressed by the action, which we perceive as a sign of an ethical virtue
or character, our mind is delighted and exalted, presuming of course that we are also agents interested in the
promotion of ethical virtues in general. Respect for traditional rites of mourning and sacrifices is an expression for
the concern with ren and li, because such practices exemplify the Confucian ideal of humanity; it is a sort of
religious concern without endorsing any religious beliefs and practices.
8 The Confucian tradition
If the set of li, or rules of proper conduct, is viewed as a repository of traditional insights, a question then arises
concerning the Confucians' conception of their own tradition. Like other enduring ethical or religious traditions
which extend across history (such as Buddhism or Christianity), the Confucian or Ru tradition, as embodied in the
notion of daotong, has often been the target of the contemporary critique. According to one familiar appraisal, the
Ru tradition is out of tune with our times. Like any cherished cultural artefact, it is best revered as a relic of the
past. Moreover, many adherents of the Confucian tradition are dogmatic; they are unwilling to accept reasonable
proposal for change or modification of some components of the tradition.
Replying to this charge, a Confucian thinker or scholar might point out that, to a certain extent, the critique is
reasonable. Throughout its long history, there is a recurrent tendency of many adherents of the Confucian tradition
to institute orthodoxy and uphold their perceived values of the tradition as the true values of the tradition,
indifferent to the distinction between perceived and real values. A personal ascription of value to an object cannot
be logically equated with the value inherent in the object. Understanding a living tradition requires an appreciation
of the distinction between the actual past and the perceived past, and the distinction between a living, robust
tradition and a dying, decaying tradition. In the words of Jaroslav Pelikan, ‘Tradition is the living faith of the
dead, traditionalism is the dead faith of the living' (Pelikan 1984: 65).
Confucianism, in the words of Thomé Fang, is ‘a constructive philosophy of comprehensive harmony invested
with creative energies of life' (Fang 1981: 33). Although this is a summary statement of the outcome of Fang's
metaphysical inquiry, it is an apt characterization of the vitality of the Confucian dao or way as an ethical vision of
the good human life, an ideal amenable to varying interpretations of its concrete significance in different times and
places. Dao is an ideal theme rather than an ideal norm or supreme principle of conduct (Cua 1978, ch. 8). It is
fundamentally a unifying perspective for harmonizing the diverse elements of moral experience. To adopt the dao
is to see human life, in its morally excellent form, as possessing a coherence in which apparently conflicting
elements are viewed as eligible components of an achievable harmonious order (Cua 1982, ch. 3). It is this vision
of dao that renders intelligible the idea of a Confucian ethical tradition as a living tradition enriched by its historic
past, interpreted by adherents as having a present and prospective significance ( Dao).
9 Xunzi and Zhu Xi
Xunzi and Zhu Xi are perhaps the most articulate proponents of the importance of learning the classics as an
indispensable means to inculcating a respect for the historical aspect of tradition. Xunzi points out that learning is
an unceasing process of accumulation of goodness, knowledge, and practical understanding: ‘If an ethically
superior person (junzi) studies widely and daily engages in self-examination, his intellect will become enlightened
and his conduct be without fault.' In general, the programme of learning ‘commences with the recitation of the
classics and ends with the study of li (rituals)'. Its purpose, however, is ‘first to learn to become a scholar and
ultimately to become a sage'. The classics are presumed to embody the concrete significance of dao. For example,
‘the Odes give expression to the will (zhi) or determination [to realize dao]; the History or Book of Documents to
its significance in human affairs; the Li or Rites to its significance in conduct; the Music to its significance in
promoting harmony; and the Spring and Autumn Annals to its subtleties.' Notably, these classics are not
self-explanatory, thus guidance from perceptive teachers is required. For example, ‘the Li and Music present us
with models, but no explanations; the Odes and the History deal with ancient matters and are not always pertinent;
the Spring and Autumn Annals are terse and cannot be quickly understood' (Xunzi I, in Li 1979: 2-14; trans. in
Watson 1963: 15-20).
Indeed, for Confucius as for Mencius and Xunzi, the li represent an ethical and cultural tradition ( Confucius).
Learning to be a moral agent consists in part in appreciating ‘the accumulated wisdom of the past'. Compliance
with li as a set of formal prescriptions of proper behaviour without regard to ren and particular circumstances
would be deemed unreasonable. It is perhaps for this reason that Confucius stresses yi (a sense of rightness) rather
than preconceived opinions in coping with novel and exigent situations. Mencius is emphatic that the relevance of
a li-requirement must be considered in the light of weighing (quan) particular circumstances. In a similar spirit,
Xunzi emphasizes the exercise of yi in responding to changing circumstances of human life. In general, the
enforcement of laws and other rules of conduct depends on superior or exemplary persons (junzi) who have not
only a knowledge of the subject matter but also an understanding of their underlying purposes, in addition to
having a sense of priority and an ability to respond appropriately to changing affairs. Learning to become a sage
(shengren) must begin with the study of the classics with a view to discerning their actuating significance in living
contexts ( Chinese Classics).
The Confucian respect for the authority of the past in relation to the present requires not only a critical
understanding of the practical significance of the classics but, more importantly, a critical assessment of the ethical
character and achievement of contemporary adherents of the tradition. Thus Xunzi urges his readers to distinguish
common people from three sorts of Confucians (Ru): the vulgar or conventional (suru), the refined or cultured
(yaru) and the great or sagely Confucians (daru). This distinction between three types of Confucians may be seen
to be motivated by Xunzi's desire to respond to the internal challenges within the Confucian tradition - a reminder
and a warning to his fellow Confucians against uncritical intellectual and practical affiliation (Xunzi VIII, in Li
1979). His critique of Mencius on the relation between morality and human nature is a well-known illustration of
an internal conflict between different interpretations of a key aspect of Confucian ethical tradition. Like Mencius,
Xunzi is also quite aware of the need to engage in argumentation to answer external challenges to the Confucian
tradition (Xunzi XXIII, in Li 1979). For Mencius, there was no alternative but to engage in disputation since the
dao of the sages, embodied in Yao and Shun, had in his own time been obscured by the prevailing teachings of
Yang Zhu and Mozi.
In a similar spirit, Xunzi attacks the views of a number of philosophers, for example, Mozi, Hui Shi, Songzi and
Shen Dao, as well as Laozi and Zhuangzi. Xunzi considers most of their doctrines pernicious because, though
often presented in elegant language and composition, they also present erroneous conceptions of the distinction
between right and wrong and between order and disorder. However, it is noteworthy that Xunzi's critique
explicitly acknowledges that ‘some of what they advocate has a reasoned basis, and thus their statements appear
plausible' (Xunzi VI, in Li 1979: 94). In the light of his holistic conception of dao, many philosophical views are
unacceptable not because they are totally erroneous, but because they grasp only partial aspects of dao and
exaggerate these at the expense of other aspects. In sum, in Xunzi we find a Confucian philosopher who
exemplifies a concern with defending the Confucian tradition against both internal and external challenges, and
who is at the same time quite capable of critical adoption of non-Confucian views which he deems reasonably
acceptable.
Zhu Xi's conception of the Confucian tradition, daotong, commonly rendered as ‘transmission of dao', is a
conception central to the orthodox tradition of neo-Confucianism ( Neo-Confucian philosophy). Because of its
religious connotation, the notion of orthodoxy quite naturally suggests an uncritical adherence to conventional or
currently accepted beliefs as possessing an unquestioned authoritative status. As de Bary has instructively shown,
however, daotong is better construed as ‘repossession of dao' or ‘reconstitution of dao', recalling Pelikan's
distinction between a living tradition and traditionalism (de Bary 1981: 2).
As Tu Wei-ming remarks, Zhu Xi's study of the classics represents ‘serious efforts to revitalize the tradition
[which] involved creative adaptation as well as faithful interpretations' (Tu 1979: 134). For example, in his
detailed recommendations of classics for examinations, apart from some commentaries, Zhu Xi stresses the
self-critical study of original texts: ‘In studying the classics one must have regard for the considered views of
former scholars and extrapolate from them, aware that they are not necessarily conclusive but must be weighed as
to what they understood and what they missed; then finally all this must be reflected upon in one's own mind to
verify it' (Zhuzi yulei 3:37, in Li 1962, 1638-42). Zhu Xi also recommends non-orthodox philosophers of early
China such as Xunzi, Han Feizi, Laozi ( Daodejing) and Zhuangzi. De Bary rightly reminds us that Zhu Xi's
notion of daotong should not be construed in a manner that suggests a passive reception and transmission of the
Confucian Way, for it involves an activity of revitalization and rediscovery as well as recovery of the meaning of
the tradition or, in contemporary language, an activity of constructive or reconstructive interpretation of the
tradition: ‘In fact, Chu Hsi [Zhu Xi] emphasized the discontinuities in the tradition almost more than the
continuities, and underscored the contributions of inspired individuals who rediscovered or "clarified" the Way in
new forms' (de Bary 1981: 99).
Both Xunzi and Zhu Xi emphasize the role of inspired and insightful persons regarding classical learning. This
emphasis somewhat echoes Confucius' notion of junzi or paradigmatic individuals, that is, persons, who through
their life and conduct embody ren, li, yi and other ethical excellences ( §2). The junzi are the exemplars of the
actuating significance of the Confucian tradition, serving as standards of inspiration for committed agents. These
paradigmatic individuals are generally ascribed an authority by their contemporary adherents. The authority,
however, is based on the acknowledgement of their superior knowledge and achievement, and especially their
exercise of yi in interpretive judgements concerning the relevance of rules in exigent situations, or in Xunzi's
words, on dao and de (virtue). However, while possessed of an authoritative ethical status, as standard bearers and
interpreters of culture the junzi are not arbiters of moral disputes, for their interpretations of the Confucian
tradition represent individual efforts toward the repossession or reconstitution of dao, thus essentially contestable
and subject to reasoned assessment of their contemporaries and posterity.
Implicit in the foregoing characterization of the Confucian tradition as a living tradition is the notion of tradition as
an interpretive concept. For the most part, major Confucian philosophers stress the importance of classical
education and the role of teachers as junzi or paradigmatic individuals, because they are thought to exemplify the
best spirit of Confucius. Notably, Confucius' conception of junzi focuses on some salient characteristics. In
addition to their pursuit of dao, the concern with ren, li and yi, they are also persons of integrity, catholicity and
neutrality. The integrity is exemplified in their unwavering concern with the harmony of words and deeds (Cua
1978, ch. 5). This stress on the role of junzi as a guiding standard of education and moral conduct naturally gives
rise to the question on the possibility of modification and transformation of the Confucian tradition. Indeed, if
tradition is an interpretive concept, some account must be given on how changes may be viewed as consistent with
the conservation of tradition.
10 Transformation of the Confucian tradition
In the Confucian context, this problem of transformation of the tradition is best considered in terms of the
distinction and connection between jing (the standard) and quan (the weighing of circumstances). The former
pertains to the operative, established standards of conduct, the latter to the specific circumstances. Quan may be
regarded as jing prior to the determination of its significance in actual, particular situations. In other words, jing,
the established standards of conduct, depend on quan in the sense that their application is undetermined prior to
actual circumstances. When such a determination is made, quan would become part of jing, given the assumption
that the judgments are accepted by the Confucian community of interpretation. Concisely put, jing is the
determinate quan, and quan is the indeterminate jing. Of course, both represent the constant (chang) and the
changing (bian) aspects of dao.
More importantly, the exercise of quan entails a concern with yi or rightness of judgement. Right judgement is
necessary not only in dealing with the hard cases of the moral life, but also with normal situations (jing) where the
intelligent adherent of the tradition confronts the problem of interpretation and application. In both sorts of
situation the agent has the same moral objective, that is, to do the right thing. This is perhaps the point of Zhu Xi's
saying that quan is unavoidably exercised in changing situations that fall outside the scope of the regular practice
of daoli (moral norm):
When quan attains equilibrium (zhong), it does not differ from jing', that is, they have achieved the same moral
objective. In both cases they are governed by the exercise of yi or one's sense of rightness. For Zhu Xi, yi
constitutes the guan, the thread that runs though jing and quan.
(Zhuzi yulei 3:37, in Li 1962, 1638-42)
The foregoing reflections on the distinction and connection between jing and quan afford us an answer to the
question of the possibility of change or modification of the Confucian tradition of dao. Intelligent adherents of the
Confucian tradition can deploy the sceptical challenge without fear of the corruption of the tradition ( Moral
scepticism). The dynamic interplay of jing and quan in relation to constancy (chang) and change (bian) shows that
the distinction is not a fixed or absolute distinction. As Dai Zhen points out, what is deemed important or
unimportant in our assessment will vary in different times and places (Dai 1777 [1975]: 125). Put differently, the
substantive content of the tradition of dao cannot be considered settled without prejudging the merits of particular
circumstances. The exercise of quan in any situation requires a careful examination and analysis of all the relevant
factors involved.
Quite naturally, one may raise the question of justification for such judgements in exigent circumstances. In
normal situations, the li are quite sufficient for action guidance insofar as they are informed by a concern for ren.
The problem of reasoned justification for such judgments has not received attention from most Confucian thinkers,
except Xunzi. However, even in the works of Xunzi we do not find any articulate answer to this problem, though
his works do provide materials for constructing a response. In the first place, Xunzi is explicit that any discussion
is valuable because there exist certain standards for assessment, and these standards pertain principally to
conceptual clarity, respect for linguistic practices and evidence, and the requirement of consistency and coherence
in discourse. A philosophical reconstruction along the lines of the theory of argumentation presents an interesting
Confucian view of justification in terms of rational and empirical standards of competence, along with certain
desirable qualities of participants in ethical discourse. In this reconstruction of Xunzi's works, ethical justification
is a phase of discourse, preceded by explanatory efforts in the clarification of normative claims responsive to a
problem of common concern among participants. This in turn presupposes that queries concerning the proper uses
of terms are understood by participants in ethical argumentation (Cua 1985a).
11 Historical appeal
As widely noted by contemporary writers on Confucian ethics, in argumentative discourse the Confucians are fond
of appeal to historical events and paradigmatic individuals. This ethical use of historical knowledge and beliefs is a
pervasive feature of Confucianism. A serious student of Chinese philosophy cannot accept the common view that
Chinese thinkers are inclined to be uncritical towards their history, or that they believe that history provides the
exclusive guidance for present problems and perplexities. A careful examination of the works of Xunzi refutes this
thesis. The Confucian respect for tradition and its history, and for exemplary historical persons and events, is best
appreciated in terms of four ethical, argumentative uses of the past or historical appeal. These are the pedagogical,
rhetorical, elucidative and evaluative uses ( History, Chinese theories of).
For Xunzi, the primary aim of moral education is the transformation of man's native but problematic motivational
structure (for example, feelings and desires) by way of knowledge of standards of ren, yi and li. One learns for the
sake of doing; knowing the right and the good is for the sake of acting in accord with such knowledge. Learning,
however, is not equivalent to the mere acquisition of knowledge but more essentially requires understanding and
insight. For Xunzi, the basic philosophical issue in moral education pertains to the rational coordination of the
intellectual and volitional activities of the mind (xin) by means of the dao. Given the autonomy of mind, one can
choose to accept or reject its guidance. If the mind is directed by reason and nourished with clarity and is not
perturbed by extraneous matters, ‘it will be capable of determining right and wrong and of resolving doubts'
(Xunzi XXI, in Li 1979: 490; trans. in Watson 1963: 131). In sum, the pedagogical use of the historical appeal
points not only to models who are worthy or unworthy of emulation, but more significantly to models functioning
as reminders in moral learning and conduct that appeal especially to what is deemed in the real interests of the
learner. Notably, gentle suasion rather than coercion is involved, as the individual still retains the freedom to
accept or reject it. This constitutes the argumentative value of the pedagogical function of the historical appeal
rather than the mere exhibition of moral exemplars. The latter's effectiveness lies primarily in the appeal to
paradigmatic individuals (junzi) ( Moral education; Moral development).
The rhetorical function of the historical appeal is essentially a problem of assurance, of appeal to plausible
presumptions or shared beliefs and trustworthiness (xin) ( Xin). When I present reasons supporting my
interpretation of the Confucian tradition, I will deploy those unquestioned assumptions in discourse. Also, I expect
my fellow Confucians to believe me when I cite information that is presumably known to members of my
community. Obviously, the historical appeal functions as a technique for assuring the audience that the thesis
maintained is consonant with shared historical beliefs, and obviates having to state reasons for their support. It also
constitutes a technique of discounting alternative views, shifting the burden of proof to a possible adversary. These
uses, of course, are subject to further challenge, for the rational acceptability of the thesis and an assurance that the
thesis is not a mere imaginative contrivance to avoid questioning.
The elucidative function of the use of history attempts to clarify the relevance of the past for the present. This is
basically an expression of the respect for tradition, clarifying, in interpretation, one's intelligent, critical
understanding of the tradition. Of course, the question of evaluation arises in serious Confucian discourse. Inherent
in the use of historical characters for elucidating and demonstrating the applicability of an ethical thesis is the
implicit claim that human history is the proper subject of ethical appraisal. However, this claim is explicit in the
evaluative use of the historical appeal.
Notably, the elucidative use of the historical appeal is retrospective; that is, it is the use of the appeal to the past for
judging the present (yigu chijin); while the evaluative use is prospective, that is, for the sake of determining the
relevance of the past to the present (yijin chigu). In the retrospective use, Xunzi is clearly recommending the
adoption of a standpoint based on historical knowledge or beliefs for the purpose of maintaining or assessing the
adequacy of current beliefs. The prospective use, however, stresses our knowledge and understanding of our
present problematic situations as a basis for assessing the unexamined claims based on the past as a guidance to the
present. Both the retrospective and prospective uses of the historical appeal are essentially critical, and can be used
either in the positive defence of one's thesis or in the negative evaluation of another's thesis or both. In J.O.
Urmson's words, we have here a distinction between standard-invoking and standard-setting aspects of normative
discourse (Urmson 1968: 68). In effect, the retrospective use of the historical appeal invokes an established
framework with its operative criteria or standards for justification of ethical judgments. Of course, one can always
raise external questions about an established practice.
The prospective use of the historical appeal reverses the standpoint of the retrospective one. Human history is seen
as a subject matter rather than as a basis for ethical judgment. In adopting this standpoint, one can no longer avail
oneself of the presumption of the truth of historical beliefs without critical examination, nor can one presume the
existence of shared historical knowledge. The key issue here lies in the present evidential grounding of ethical
claims (for further discussion see Cua 1985b).
In closing, it may be noted that Confucian ethics, like any normative system, presents conceptual problems of
interpretation and reconstruction. Attention here has been focused on the Confucian scheme of basic notions and
the idea of Confucian tradition (daotong). Doing full justice to the range of Confucian concerns also involves a
critical consideration of divergent views on such topics as the relation of the basic notions to human nature, the
role of emotions in ethical deliberation and justification, the place of law in an ideal social, political union, and the
metaphysical grounding of dao, particularly in the connection of the human and the natural orders. A serious
student of Confucian philosophy must consider these problems with reference both to the divisive efforts and
tension within the history of Chinese philosophy, and to the significance of these efforts to of Western
philosophical inquiries.